Thou shalt not kill; but needst not strive/ Officiously to keep alive.”
Arthur Clough’s famous lines, taken out of context, have been the
legitimating thought behind non-voluntary euthanasia. In a landmark
ruling in Aruna Ramchandra Shanbaug vs Union of India, the Supreme Court
has created a legal framework for passive, non-voluntary euthanasia
under very strict conditions. High courts can now entertain petitions to
withdraw life support of patients in what is known as persistent
vegetative state (PVS). They will follow certain procedural guidelines
in ascertaining whether such petitions should be granted. These
procedural guidelines require a case to be heard by at least a two-judge
bench and include seeking the opinion of a panel of three doctors,
consulting relatives but not regarding their view as binding.
The case itself is searingly difficult. The extremes of human nature
converge in the judgment: the extraordinary brutality of the crime that
put Aruna Shanbaug in a vegetative state meets the quite extraordinary
kindness of the KEM hospital staff. The judgment is balanced and clearly
argued. It honours existing Indian law that renders active euthanasia
and suicide illegal. It merely suggests that attempted suicide should
not be criminalised. But in the absence of an elaborate domestic law, it
relies on the “persuasive value” of foreign rulings, particularly
Airedale NHS trust vs Bland from the United Kingdom. But as in any
judgment on a difficult case, more questions will have to be resolved as
the guidelines are implemented.
Although the court relies heavily on the Airedale case, it is
something of a pity that the court did not provide more guidelines on
dealing with issues concerning PVS that have arisen since the case was
decided. The determination of when PVS obtains is itself contested. But
while the court has set up a process, it can be asked whether it has
given sufficient substantive guidelines to high courts. Even those
jurisdictions that permit passive euthanasia have different attitudes
towards different ways of letting die. Peter McCullagh’s comprehensive
study of the medical and legal issues surrounding PVS found that doctors
across national jurisdictions have very different attitudes towards two
ways of letting die. Some doctors make a distinction between the
appropriateness of not treating acute infections and other
life-threatening conditions on the one hand, and withdrawal of
artificial hydration and nutrition on the other. So the question of
appropriate method still remains. Courts will now enter uncharted
territory when it comes to PVS.
Second, the ground of the judgment is very narrow, perhaps
appropriately so. Although the discussion starts off with references to
the right to die with dignity, conceptions of dignity play no role in
the argument. The argument does not rest on the proposition that the
justification for letting die is to mitigate the suffering of the
patient or to honour their dignity. The worry about these arguments is
that they open the door for voluntary euthanasia. The argument, in this
instance, seems to go like this. Under certain circumstances (PVS), no
interest is served by prolonging life and therefore there is no
obligation to do so. Why is there no interest? Because it is futile to
expect the patient can recover from PVS. The idea of “futility” is
deeply complex. But the interesting question is whether the futility
standard will be a necessary condition for courts to entertain any
euthanasia appeal. Will this, rather than dignity or suffering-based
arguments, underlie euthanasia jurisprudence?
Should this also play out in standards that should apply to when
we should accept a patient’s own refusal of treatment? The court leaves
open the question whether not taking food consciously and voluntarily
with the aim of ending one’s life is a crime. But here’s the
complication. If it is not a crime, can the state “force feed”? If there
is no obligation to prevent death as the court suggests, would
force-feeding presumptively count as a violation of rights? The judgment
hints rightly that we do not have a unified framework for thinking
about these issues.
Third, the judgment reveals interesting attitudes towards the
meaning of a patient’s life. The court rules that Aruna’s life not be
terminated since the medical staff at KEM hospital are the only ones who
can bring a petition in this respect. They are bearing the costs of the
treatment and are quite happy to do so. But, more importantly, Aruna’s
continuing life has meaning for them. These are powerful considerations.
But there is still something disquieting about the fact that PVS cases
test the limits of any standard of life that is patient-centred. In PVS
cases, usually costs are an important consideration. Where no benefit
can come from treatment and the costs are perhaps prohibitively high,
life may not be prolonged. Second, someone must wish it prolonged
because the existence of the patient, even in PVS, is fraught with
meaning. Both of these considerations unwittingly reveal the sense in
which the value of life is not intrinsic. It depends, in extreme
circumstances, upon costs; and it depends upon whether someone cares for
you. When these circumstances obtain is highly variable. Judges cannot
be expected to compensate for all the ethical irrationalities of the
world. But this case is a stark reminder of how often life is valued,
not from the agent’s perspective but from the social valence placed upon
it.
The judgment relies on the philosophical distinction between acts
and omissions. To be very honest, there is a bit of re-descriptive
casuistry at work in applying this distinction to PVS cases — the cause
of death is not some underlying disease that is allowed to take its
course; the cause is the act of withdrawal. We should be ambivalent
about this distinction. For many this distinction leads to an evasion of
responsibility. It allows us to get away with the thought that we are
not responsible for deaths to others even though our acts could have
possibly prevented them. But this distinction is a reminder of our own
smallness and finitude. To say that there is no distinction between acts
and omissions, and the prohibitions that apply to killing should also
apply to omissions, would require us to be more than human. Perhaps
those lingering at the edge of life teach us this: we still cannot fully
make sense of the ethical structures we inhabit. But in the meantime we
should be grateful that the court has at least given a mechanism with
plausible safeguards to adjudicate these difficult questions. Few things
are more inhuman than not even getting a hearing.
The writer is president, Centre for Policy Research, Delhi
0 Comments