Legal Realism
The legal realist movement was inspired by John Chipman Gray and
Oliver Wendall Holmes and reached its apex in the 1920s and 30s through
the work of Karl Llewellyn, Jerome Frank, and Felix Cohen. The realists
eschewed the conceptual approach of the positivists and naturalists in
favor of an empirical analysis that sought to show how practicing judges
really decide cases (see Leiter 1998). The realists were
deeply skeptical of the ascendant notion that judicial legislation is a
rarity. While not entirely rejecting the idea that judges can be
constrained by rules, the realists maintained that judges create new law
through the exercise of lawmaking discretion considerably more often
than is commonly supposed. On their view, judicial decision is guided
far more frequently by political and moral intuitions about the facts of
the case (instead of by legal rules) than theories like positivism and
naturalism acknowledge.
As an historical matter, legal realism arose in response to legal formalism,
a particular model of legal reasoning that assimilates legal reasoning
to syllogistic reasoning. According to the formalist model, the legal
outcome (that is, the holding) logically follows from the legal rule
(major premise) and a statement of the relevant facts (minor premise).
Realists believe that formalism understates judicial lawmaking abilities
insofar as it represents legal outcomes as entailed
syllogistically by applicable rules and facts. For if legal outcomes are
logically implied by propositions that bind judges, it follows that
judges lack legal authority to reach conflicting outcomes.
Legal realism can roughly be characterized by the following claims:
- the class of available legal materials is insufficient to logically entail a unique legal outcome in most cases worth litigating at the appellate level (the Local Indeterminacy Thesis);
- in such cases, judges make new law in deciding legal disputes through the exercise of a lawmaking discretion (the Discretion Thesis); and
- judicial decisions in indeterminate cases are influenced by the judge’s political and moral convictions, not by legal considerations.
Though (3) is logically independent of (1) and (2), (1) seems to
imply (2): insofar as judges decide legally indeterminate cases, they
must be creating new law.
It is worth noting the relations between legal realism, formalism,
and positivism. While formalism is often thought to be entailed by
positivism, it turns out that legal realism is not only consistent with
positivism, but also presupposes the truth of all three of positivism’s
core theses. Indeed, the realist acknowledges that law is essentially
the product of official activity, but believes that judicial lawmaking
occurs more frequently than is commonly assumed. But the idea that law
is essentially the product of official activity presupposes the truth of
positivism’s Conventionality, Social Fact, and Separability theses.
Though the preoccupations of the realists were empirical (that is,
attempting to identify the psychological and sociological factors
influencing judicial decision-making), their implicit conceptual
commitments were decidedly positivistic in flavor.
b. Critical Legal Studies
The critical legal studies (CLS) movement attempts to expand the
radical aspects of legal realism into a Marxist critique of mainstream
liberal jurisprudence. CLS theorists believe the realists understate the
extent of indeterminacy; whereas the realists believe that
indeterminacy is local in the sense that it is confined to a certain
class of cases, CLS theorists argue that law is radically (or globally)
indeterminate in the sense that the class of available legal materials
rarely, if ever, logically/causally entails a unique outcome.
CLS theorists emphasize the role of ideology in shaping the content
of the law. On this view, the content of the law in liberal democracies
necessarily reflects “ideological struggles among social factions in
which competing conceptions of justice, goodness, and social and
political life get compromised, truncated, vitiated, and adjusted”
(Altman 1986, p. 221). The inevitable outcome of such struggles, on this
view, is a profound inconsistency permeating the deepest layers of the
law. It is this pervasive inconsistency that gives rise to radical
indeterminacy in the law. For insofar as the law is inconsistent, a
judge can justify any of a number of conflicting outcomes.
At the heart of the CLS critique of liberal jurisprudence is the idea
that radical indeterminacy is inconsistent with liberal conceptions of
legitimacy. According to these traditional liberal conceptions, the
province of judges is to interpret, and not make, the law. For, on this
view, democratic ideals imply that lawmaking must be left to legislators
who, unlike appointed judges, are accountable to the electorate. But if
law is radically indeterminate, then judges nearly always decide cases
by making new law, which is inconsistent with liberal conceptions of the
legitimate sources of lawmaking authority.
0 Comments