"Before they addressed themselves to the
impractical task of changing men by changing laws, the justices might
have pondered the words of Savigny, who wrote, 'Law is no more made
by lawyers than language by grammarians. Law is the natural moral product
of a people . . . the persistent customs of a nation, springing organically
from its past and present. Even statute law lives in the general consensus
of the people.'" -Wilmot Robertson, The Dispossessed Majority (1981)
The concept of the Volksgeist, or "the spirit of
the Volk," was developed by
German philosopher Johann Gottfried von Herder (1744-1803). The application
of Herder's theory to law was made by German jurist and legal historian
Friedrich Karl von Savigny (1779-1861).
Herder's Volksgeist is a manifestation of
the people; it animates the nation. Every Volk is, as an empirical matter,
different from every other Volk, each nationality characterized
by its own unique spirit. Every people possesses its own cultural traits
shaped by ancestral history and the experience of a specific physical
environment, and mentally constructs its social life through language,
law, literature, religion, the arts, customs, and folklore inherited
from earlier generations. The Volk, in other words, is the
family writ large.
Laws, too, must be adapted
to the spirit of each nation, for rules applied to one nation are not
valid for another. The only legitimate governments are those that develop
naturally among particular nations and reflect, in their differences
from other polities, the cultures of the people they govern.
Law is the unique creation
of a race, a people, a Volk. Like language or values,
it is the result of collective human action and reason over generations,
not the result of human design. Language and law were never consciously
invented at a specific moment in time. Rather, they represent slow accumulations,
organic emanations of discrete peoples.
To cite but one example,
European law and values and Jewish law and values are as different as
night and day. In adopting torture, assassination, criminalization of
free speech, thought, and association, genocide, and the abolition of
formal restraints on tyranny, whites overnight lost half a millennium
or more of slow, painful moral and legal progress.
Descendant of Landed Nobility
Savigny was the descendant
of a distinguished Huguenot family from Lorraine, in France, which moved
to Germany in 1730 to escape Catholic intolerance. The family derived
its name from the Castle of Savigny in the valley of the Moselle River;
its members retained their German allegiance upon the transfer of Lorraine
to France.
Savigny was born in Frankfurt,
the son of a Lutheran father and a Calvinist mother. Orphaned at thirteen,
without parents or siblings, the boy was raised by his father's best
friend, a prominent German attorney and government official who, from
the age of 15, plunged Savigny and his own son "into a terrible
course [of education], comprising the science of law, natural law, international
law, Roman law, and German law"--an experience Savigny's chroniclers
compare to John Stuart Mill's über-rigorous schooling.
Graduating from the University
of Marburg in 1800, Savigny took up teaching at the same institution.
Among his students were the brothers Jacob and Wilhelm Grimm, the later
philologists and mythologists famous for Grimm's Fairy Tales. Savigny eventually secured a position for
Jacob at the University of Berlin, and the two maintained a correspondence.
Jacob Grimm dedicated his masterwork, Deutsche Grammatik, one of the most important works of German
philology ever written, to Savigny.
Savigny married into the
famous Brentano family. One of his wife's nephews, pacifist economist
Ludwig Brentano, won the Nobel Peace Prize in 1927. Savigny's brother-in-law
was the writer Clemens Brentano, and his sister-in-law was Bettina von
Arnim, correspondent of Goethe and wife of romantic poet and novelist
Achim von Arnim. Through his in-laws Savigny came into close contact
with the Heidelberg group of Romantic writers. Savigny's son, Karl Friedrich
von Savigny (1814-1875), was a prominent Prussian diplomat and politician.
In 1810 Savigny became
Professor of Roman Law at Prussia's newly-formed University of Berlin
at the request of Wilhelm von Humboldt. There he helped found the institution,
served as its first Rector, and organized the law faculty. He also taught
the Crown Prince, subsequently King Frederick William IV of Prussia.
Savigny's highly influential
legal works include The Law of Possession (Das Recht des Besitzes) (1803), History of Roman Law in
the Middle Ages (Geschichte des römischen
Rechts im Mittelalter), 6 vols. (1815-1831),
in which he traced the history of Roman law from the breakup of the
empire until the beginning of the 12th century and showed how it lived
on in local customs, towns, ecclesiastical doctrines, and school teachings
until its reemergence in the Renaissance, System of Modern Roman
Law (System des heutigen römischen
Rechts), 8 vols. (1840-1849),
an uncompleted work on the contemporary Roman law of Europe, Miscellaneous Writings (Vermischte Schriften), 5 vols. (1850), and The Law of Contracts (Das Obligationenrecht), 2 vols. (1851-53).
As Jewish law professor
Milton R. Konvitz noted:
His massive work on Roman
law in the Middle Ages became the source of subjects for countless historical
monographs. His students, and their students in turn, dominated historical
and legal scholarship and teaching for several generations, and he was
universally acknowledged as one of the most influential thinkers and
scholars of the nineteenth century.
Civil Law and Common Law
Historically, there has
been a disjunction between the civil law systems of continental Europe
and the common law systems characteristic of England and the English-settled
countries.
Civil law is based upon
Roman law, which was first codified in the Twelve Tables in 450 B.C.
Codification was completed in 535 A.D. in the Corpus Juris Civilis, the culminating work of Roman legal scholarship.
After the fall of the Western
Roman Empire, Roman law persisted as part of Germanic law, the customary
law of the ancient Germans (codified in the 5th-9th centuries A.D.),
and canon law, the law of the Roman Catholic Church courts. It also
remained the law of the Eastern Roman Empire, centered in modern-day
Turkey, until its collapse in 1453.
The revival of classical
studies during the Renaissance led to the resurrection of Roman law,
as the Corpus Juris Civilis became the model for most of the legal systems
of continental Europe.
The civil law system of
the continent was thus a mixture of Roman law and local customary law.
As a committee of legal historians observed in 1914:
The story of Western Continental
Law is made up, in the last analysis, of two great movements, racial
and intellectual. One is the Germanic migrations, planting a solid growth
of Germanic custom everywhere, from Danzig to Sicily, from London to
Vienna. The other is the posthumous power of Roman law, forever resisting,
struggling, and coalescing with the other.
The importance of Roman
law, Savigny wrote, is that "by reason of its high state of cultivation"
it serves as a pattern for modern jurists. The importance of the local
or customary law is that "it is directly and popularly connected
with us." Examination of the historical modifications of the two
systems demonstrates how both Roman law and local law varied under the
stress of actual needs and the application of legal theory.
Eventually, a single European
civil code may replace existing national codes, and Savigny figures
in current discussions about this. Here,
for example, is Belgian law professor,
former Advocate General of the European Court of Justice in Luxembourg,
and general editor of a series of casebooks on the Common law of Europe Walter van Gerven writing for the European Commission:
The opposition between
von Savigny and Thibaut [see below], regarded as an opposition between
law, seen as a product of history, and law, seen as a product
of reason, is somehow reflected
in the opposition nowadays between those who believe that cultural differences
between Member States and legal mentalities are such that no codification
at European level is possible, at least not for the time being, and
those who believe that codification has to come about without further
delay. (p. 9)
To help overcome this difficulty,
it has been suggested by some that Savigny's historical school of law
should be reconstituted on a pan-European level. (E.g., Reinhard Zimmerman,
"Savigny's Vermächtnis, Rechtsgeschichte, Rechtsvergleichung und
die Begdindung einer Europäischen Rechtswissenschaft" ["Savigny's
Legacy, Legal History, Unification of Law and Preconditions for European
Legal Sciences"], Juristische Blätter [1998], 273.)
As an aside, it is instructive
to briefly touch upon the Pan-European method behind this endeavor as
described by van Gerven:
Work that is already underway
should be continued on an even larger scale with "the aim of finding
a European common core of legal principles and rules" and starting
with the modest task of "mark(ing) out areas of agreement and disagreement,
to construct a European legal lingua franca that has concepts large enough to embrace legal
institutions which are functionally comparable, to develop a truly common
law literature and the beginnings of a European law school curriculum."
(p. 29)
The author continues: "That
this is not an easy matter appears from the literature on [European]
Community law which now flourishes abundantly in any one Member State,
but unfortunately very often in a closed national, or one language,
circuit without reference to literature published in other Member States
or other languages." (p. 29n)
This shows how even the
largest European institutions, with ample access to multilingual personnel,
extensive translations, and continuous cross-border contacts and cooperation
are still stymied by deeply entrenched intra-European cultural differences--particularly
linguistic balkanization.
The situation is comparable
but far worse for white racialists with their meager resources, inability
to communicate in multiple languages, and lack of international contacts.
Indeed, when racialists try to establish even one-off personal connections
they are often hounded mercilessly by Jewish organizations, communist
street thugs, pliant politicians and journalists, and police agencies
determined to strangle white unity in the cradle. Victims of such actions
have included Francis Parker Yockey, George Lincoln Rockwell, William
Pierce, Tom and John Metzger, David Irving, and many others.
Unfortunately, any new
Pan-European laws promulgated by existing elites will be deeply inimical
to white racial survival and fundamental human rights.
The Origin of Germany's
Codification Controversy
There have been many modern
codifications of civil law principles, the most famous and influential
of which is the Code Napoléon (1804) of France, which strongly shaped
the civil law systems of continental Europe and Latin America.
Louisiana is the only US
civil law state, its law based upon French and Spanish codes and ultimately
Roman law as opposed to English common law. Similarly, in Canada, French
Quebec is the only province that operates under a dual system, with
civil matters being governed by continental-style civil law and criminal
matters by common law. The legal system of white South Africa was based
upon Roman-Dutch civil law, and Scotland is considered a mixed law system.
In addition to the Code
Napoléon, the major modern civil codes in effect when the German codification
controversy flared were the Prussian Landrecht (Allgemeines Landrecht für
die Preussischen Staaten, 1794) and the Austrian
General Civil Code (Allgemeines bürgerliches
Gesetzbuch, or ABGB, 1811). Today
national civil codes are prevalent almost everywhere in continental
Europe.
The primary difference
between common law and civil code systems is ideological.
Common law is based upon
precedent and gradual change, balancing tradition and reason.
The codes generally reflect
the radical, utopian hyper-rationalism of the French Revolution. The
French sought to abolish all prior law and replace it with new, all-encompassing
norms in codified form. History was deemed irrelevant to the formulation,
interpretation, and application of the French code; law ought to originate
abstractly in the human mind (pure reason). A frequently repeated maxim
of the legal radicals was, "I know nothing of the civil law; I
know only the Code Napoléon."
Theoretically the codes,
complete, coherent, and clear, reduced all law to written form. Since
lawmaking power was lodged solely in the legislature, judges could not
look outside of the code for guidance. Their duty was to mechanically
apply the law as set forth in the code.
Under the Holy Roman Empire
there had been more than 300 German states. Between 1806 and 1815, the
conqueror Napoleon organized them into the Confederation of the Rhine.
Following his defeat, the Congress of Vienna (1814-15) created the German
Confederation, consisting of 39 states, the most powerful of which were
Prussia and the Austrian Empire. Each German state had its own system
of laws which changed as you crossed the border, greatly hampering economic
and political coordination.
In 1814, A. F. J. Thibault,
professor of Roman Law at the University of Heidelberg, a former student
of Immanuel Kant's at the University of Königsberg and, like Savigny,
a German of French Huguenot descent, proposed a unified German civil
code on the French model to remedy the chaos of existing law. He set
forth his proposals in a pamphlet, About the Necessity of
a Common Civil Law for Germany (Ãœber die Nothwendigkeit
eines allgemeinen bürgerlichen Rechts für Deutschland).
Interestingly, though desirous
of enacting a uniform system of laws for the German states, Thibault
opposed political unification. As part of his proposed rationalistic
reconstruction, he favored discarding Roman law, "the work of a
nation which was very unlike us, and from the period of the lowest decline
of the same."
Opposing a French-style
code for Germany, Savigny characterized the rationalistic legal mentality
as one of "infinite arrogance" and "shallow philosophy."
Law, he maintained, could not be abstractly originated by a handful
of individuals at a specified moment in time, but is organically created
by the people of a nation as an expression of its Volksgeist. It is a grave error to
try to consciously construct an ideal, all-encompassing legal code,
to which everyone is compelled to submit. He believed that intellectuals
lacked the ability to construct humane, workable legal systems in such
a manner.
The Volksgeist and Law
Savigny set forth his views
in an epochal pamphlet, Vom Beruf unserer Zeit
für Gesetzgebung und Rechtswissenschaft (1814, 2nd rev. ed. 1828)
(Eng. trans., Frederick Charles von Savigny, Of the Vocation of Our
Age for Legislation and Jurisprudence, Abraham Hayward trans.
[London: Littlewood, 1831]) and in an introductory article to the Journal of Historical Jurisprudence (Zeitschrift für geschichtliche
Rechtswissenschaft), which he co-founded.
From 1815 to 1850 it served as the organ of the historical school of
jurisprudence.
The German Romanticism
of the early 19th century had a strong influence on Savigny's philosophy
of law. As John
Henry Merryman notes:
Savigny and his followers--influenced
by Kant, Hegel, and German Romanticism--opposed this [codification]
effort . . . Proponents of what came to be known as the "historical
school," these scholars maintained that it would be wrong for Germany
to attempt to devise a [French-style] civil code . . . In their view,
the law of a people was a historically determined organic product of
that people's development, an expression of the Volksgeist. Consequently, a thorough
study of the existing German law and of its historical development was
a necessary prelude to codification. Since the Roman civil law as interpreted
by the medieval Italian scholars had been formally received in Germany
some centuries before, a thorough historical study of German law had
to include Roman law and old Germanic law as well as more recent elements
of the contemporary German legal system. Under the influence of Savigny
and the historical school, many German scholars turned their energies
to the intensive study of legal history.
. . . The result would
be a reconstruction of the German legal system according to its inherent
principles and features.
Savigny considered law
to be an emanation of a people's spiritual and historical experience.
It "is first developed by custom and popular acceptance, next by
judicial decisions--everywhere, therefore, by internal silently operating
powers, not by the arbitrary will of the law-giver." The essential
prerequisite was a deep and far-reaching appreciation of the genius
of a particular Volk; the prescriptive content
of the law must accord with the Volksgeist.
For Savigny, German law
was an expression of the Volksgeist of the German people.
Law is only properly understood in the light of past and present history,
and reflects the inner convictions of Volk psychology and shared
moral values. The Volksgeist, constantly changing and
evolving as the German people changed and evolved, drove the slow evolution
of law over the course of history. Savigny believed that the Volk of every land had a similar
effect on each nation's law.
Legal institutions and
values, like music, art, or language, are an indigenous expression of
the culture. Savigny, like Herder, thought that there was "an organic
connection of law with the being and character of the people. . . .
Law grows with the growth, and strengthens with the strength of the
people, and finally dies away as the nation loses its nationality."
Again like Herder, the Volksgeist is best understood through
careful examination of historical data. That is why Savigny is considered
a pillar of the historical school of jurisprudence. Time and again he
traced the natural history of law, its organic growth as a living thing,
and indicated the processes by which it adjusted to the needs of successive
generations.
Although law initially
manifests through custom, as social activity and rules grow more complex
a specialist body of lawyers emerges. The lawyers who formulate law
for an advanced culture seve as the representatives of the Volksgeist. Combining historical
knowledge of law with a conceptual, systematic understanding of how
rules interrelate with one another and with the whole, jurists separate
what still has validity from that which is lifeless "and only belongs
to history," arriving thereby at a "living customary law."
Thanks in large part to
Savigny's immense influence on 19th century German law and legal scholarship,
Germany proved more resistant to the influence of the French Revolution
than any other civil law nation in Europe. The German jurist decisively
won the codification debate, and a new German Civil Code did not emerge
until 1900. When it did, its historical orientation was in marked contrast
to the revolutionary and rationalistic character of the Code Napoléon.
As Merryman explains:
The German Civil Code of
1896 [Bürgerliches
Gesetzbuch or BGB, effective 1900] is the
opposite of revolutionary. It was not intended to abolish prior law
and substitute a new legal system; on the contrary, the idea was to
codify those principles of German law that would emerge from careful
historical study of the German legal system. Instead of trying to discover
true principles of law from man's nature, as the French did . . . the
Germans sought to find fundamental principles of German law by scientific
study of the data of German law: the existing German legal system in
historical context.
The Volksgeist Abroad
No one who has studied
the works of Nobel Prize-winning Austrian economist and philosopher
Friedrich Hayek will fail to notice the parallels between his thought
and Herder's and Savigny's. In the case of Herder to cite but one example,
there are precise parallels concerning the belief in the evolution,
as opposed to the conscious invention or construction, of human languages.
Though Hayek did not articulate a racial or ethnic basis for his evolutionary
theory, he may be profitably read as if he had by anyone who recognizes
that racial universalism is incorrect and unworkable.
It is not apparent that
Hayek ever read Herder, but he was familiar with Savigny. (It is too
little appreciated that Hayek received a doctorate in law from the University
of Vienna.) Savigny's theories of law are in accord with Hayek's belief
that social phenomena such as language, law, the family, morality, the
free market, etc., objectively are (and normatively ought to be) the
"results of human action but not of human design." To attempt
conscious, rationalistic constructions in such areas of life is an error
characteristic of the totalitarian mind.
Hayek traced the influence
of Edmund Burke upon the German historical school, and, in the reverse
direction, "In the social sciences it was through Savigny's follower
Sir Henry Maine that the evolutionary approach re-entered the English
tradition."
Indeed, the common law
of the United Kingdom and the English-settled white countries was itself
an unconscious expression of the Volksgeist principle. The conservative
tendency of the common law stood in marked contrast to the revolutionary
ideology from which the continental codes emerged.
James
Coolidge Carter, a distinguished New York
attorney and opponent of 19th-century American codification, was a legal
theorist in the Savigny-Maine mold. He succinctly summarized the common
law method as follows:
It is agreed that the true
rule must somehow be found [note he says found, not
made]. Judge and advocates, all
together, engage in the search. Cases more or less nearly
approaching the one in controversy are adduced. Analogies are referred
to. The customs and habits of men are appealed to. Principles already
settled as fundamental are invoked and run out to their consequences;
and finally a rule is deduced which is declared to be the one which
the existing law requires to be applied to the case.
Another textbook example
of the Volksgeist principle in action is
Scandinavia, whose legal development has been described as follows:
Legal attitudes and legislative
practices among the Nordic peoples have been very similar, and highly
democratic, since early times. These concepts remained largely uninfluenced
by Roman law, which spread over most of the Continent. Rather, ancient
tribal laws evolved pragmatically and were passed down through generations
by word of mouth. When these laws were codified, starting about 1100,
they were found to be common regarding principles, differing only with
particular local conditions. (Norman E. Holly, "Legal and Legislative
Co-operation in the Scandinavian States," American Bar Association
Journal, November 1963, p. 1089.)
Conclusion
In his civil law casebook
(1994), John Henry Merryman asked (but did not answer) the question:
"Does a nation have only one Volksgeist or do ethnically diverse
nations have a Volksgeist for each cultural group?"
In multiracial ex-white
nations, the dominant Volk, the Jews, freely express
their Volksgeist through Jewish and general
law, but other groups are limited by the will of the rulers. This is
true even of currently favored groups like Muslims, with their Sharia
law.
But oppressed whites no
longer have a Volksgeist. Culture distortion simultaneously
destroys both the collective life of the people and its law, which is
supplanted by a rigid, racist legal positivism characteristic of contemporary
totalitarian regimes.
But if we eventually regain
our freedom and independence, Savigny's Volksgeist should inform our reacquisition
of law. The applicability to a racialist jurisprudence of a view of
law as organically evolved over time out of the consciousness or spirit
of a people is obvious.
Because biological race
consists of a system of nested hierarchies, law may be adapted to any
appropriate level of specificity or generality circumstances call for.
At present, a higher level of racial generality than was characteristic
of the old European nationalisms appears most suitable to the needs
of what is ultimately likely to be a greatly diminished, ingathered
population.
0 Comments