November 4--Kelsen II
Professor
William R. Long 11/04/04
The Pure Theory; the Basic Norm
Kelsen is
thus interested in developing a theory of law as an "ought,"
as a "science of mind." But he also wants to free his "science
of law" from methodological dependence on other "sciences
of mind." Thus, in the first page of his most famous book, The Pure Theory
of Law (1934), he says:
"It is more than two decades since I undertook the development
of a pure theory of law, that is, a theory of law purified of all political
ideology and all natural-scientific elements and conscious of its particular
character because conscious of the particular laws governing its object.
Right from the start, therefore, my aim was to raise jurisprudence,
which openly or covertly was almost completely wrapped up in legal-political
argumentation [Raisonnement], to the level of a genuine science, a science
of mind [Geistes-Wissenschaft]."
Before going
on to explain him further, however, the question should be posed. Why?
Why does one want to develop a theory of law that is "purified"
of all political ideology? Certainly he is indebted to Kant at this
point, whose Critique of Pure Reason tried to do the same for the human rational faculty, but is this
basic move that he makes helpful to those who study jurisprudence in
the 21st century?
I, for one, have taught this class from the perspective that law is
a subset of intellectual culture and that in order to understand legal
developments, one must understand them in the context of larger philosophical
and social movements of the culture. Just as Langdell was trying to
raise law to the level of a "science" or "profession"
in late 19th century America, I think that Kelsen is trying to "rescue
law" from its being just an adjunct of historical or descriptive
study. As Stewart
says, "The pure theory of law undertakes to delimit the cognition
of law against these disciplines, not because it ingores or denies the
connection, but because it wishes to avoid the uncritical mixture of
methodologically different disciplines which obscures the essence of
the science of law." At this point, we are starting to descend deeply into the arcana of German philosophical thought, and so we need
to beat a hasty retreat!
The Basic Norm (Grundnorm)
As a "science
of mind," therefore, law seeks the realm of the "ought." Kelsen is interested
in a basic principle or norm, a basic "ough," that will actually
be both descriptive and prescriptive for legal discourse. The word "norm"
can mean two things: either descriptive regularity ("You fit the
norm") or prescriptiveness ("You must obey the social norms")
[I guess there is a third meaning--the fat guy on Cheers]. Kelsen will
use the word "norm" in the prescriptive sense. When he uses the
word "normative," he means something that is prescriptive,
something that ought to be done.
What Kelsen is trying to do in developing or identifying a basic norm
is quite ambitious. In the tradition of Hegelian philosophy, which wanted
to place all cultures in a grand overarching philosophy of history according
to the principle of freedom, Kelsen wants to identify a basic legal principle which will ultimately
include or define the legal structures of all cultures. The Grundnorm
or Basic Norm is a statement against which all other duty statements
can, ultimately, be validated.
In this regard, I think that Bix's description of the Basic Norm (pp.
56-58) is excellent. The Basic Norm is ultimately a sort of act of faith--it is the belief
in a principle beyond which one cannot go and which ends up being the
foundational principle for all subsequent legal statements. You cannot "go
beyond" the Grundnorm because it is an unprovable first step (sort
of like the "democracy is best because it is democracy" approach
of 1930s-1950s American jurisprudence). Ultimately it appears that the Grundnorm for Kelsen is a belief that
one's respective legal system ought to be complied with. Lots of other
principles can then flow from this basic realization.
Conclusion--Reductionist Theories
It is a
very Germanic mode of thinking to want to get to the "essence"
of something--to identify the constitutent part that makes something
what it is. Just
as Marx wanted to collapse most societal interaction into economic relations
(which, ironically, the very conservative law and economic legal thinkers
want to do), so Kelsen wanted to isolate that one basic norm that would
underlie all legal systems. As such, he is trying to walk a tightrope between the positivist
description of law, which he does well, and a more natural law principle-based
jurisprudence.
But, more significantly I believe, Kelsen's positing of a universal
Basic Norm fueled his own study of international law. In an age like ours in 2004, where our international interdependence
is more evident each year, Kelsen's commitment to basic principles that
transcend national differences might be the fuel that stimulates ways
to make international law function better in our world.
0 Comments