Like Finnis, Lon Fuller (1964) rejects the conceptual naturalist idea that there are necessary substantive moral constraints on the content of law. But Fuller, unlike Finnis, believes that law is necessarily subject to a procedural
morality. On Fuller’s view, human activity is necessarily
goal-oriented or purposive in the sense that people engage in a
particular activity because it helps them to achieve some end. Insofar
as human activity is essentially purposive, according to Fuller,
particular human activities can be understood only in terms that make
reference to their purposes and ends. Thus, since lawmaking is
essentially purposive activity, it can be understood only in terms that
explicitly acknowledge its essential values and purposes:
The only formula that might be called a definition of law offered in these writings is by now thoroughly familiar: law is the enterprise of subjecting human conduct to the governance of rules. Unlike most modern theories of law, this view treats law as an activity and regards a legal system as the product of a sustained purposive effort (Fuller 1964, 106).
To the extent that a definition of law can be given, then, it must
include the idea that law’s essential function is to “achiev[e]
[social] order through subjecting people’s conduct to the guidance of
general rules by which they may themselves orient their behavior”
(Fuller 1965, 657).
Fuller’s functionalist conception of law implies that nothing can
count as law unless it is capable of performing law’s essential
function of guiding behavior. And to be capable of performing this
function, a system of rules must satisfy the following principles:
- (P1) the rules must be expressed in general terms;
- (P2) the rules must be publicly promulgated;
- (P3) the rules must be prospective in effect;
- (P4) the rules must be expressed in understandable terms;
- (P5) the rules must be consistent with one another;
- (P6) the rules must not require conduct beyond the powers of the affected parties;
- (P7) the rules must not be changed so frequently that the subject cannot rely on them; and
- (P8) the rules must be administered in a manner consistent with their wording.
On Fuller’s view, no system of rules that fails minimally to satisfy
these principles of legality can achieve law’s essential purpose of
achieving social order through the use of rules that guide behavior. A
system of rules that fails to satisfy (P2) or (P4), for example,
cannot guide behavior because people will not be able to determine what
the rules require. Accordingly, Fuller concludes that his eight
principles are “internal” to law in the sense that they are built into
the existence conditions for law.
These internal principles constitute a morality, according to Fuller,
because law necessarily has positive moral value in two respects: (1)
law conduces to a state of social order and (2) does so by respecting
human autonomy because rules guide behavior. Since no system of rules
can achieve these morally valuable objectives without minimally
complying with the principles of legality, it follows, on Fuller’s view,
that they constitute a morality. Since these moral principles are
built into the existence conditions for law, they are internal and
hence represent a conceptual connection between law and morality. Thus,
like the classical naturalists and unlike Finnis, Fuller subscribes to
the strongest form of the Overlap Thesis, which makes him a conceptual
naturalist.
Nevertheless, Fuller’s conceptual naturalism is fundamentally
different from that of classical naturalism. First, Fuller rejects the
classical naturalist view that there are necessary moral constraints
on the content of law, holding instead that there are necessary moral
constraints on the procedural mechanisms by which law is made and
administered: “What I have called the internal morality of law is … a
procedural version of natural law … [in the sense that it is]
concerned, not with the substantive aims of legal rules, but with the
ways in which a system of rules for governing human conduct must be
constructed and administered if it is to be efficacious and at the same
time remain what it purports to be” (Fuller 1964, 96- 97).
Second, Fuller identifies the conceptual connection between law and
morality at a higher level of abstraction than the classical
naturalists. The classical naturalists view morality as providing
substantive constraints on the content of individual laws; an unjust
norm, on this view, is conceptually disqualified from being legally
valid. In contrast, Fuller views morality as providing a constraint on
the existence of a legal system: “A total failure in any one of these
eight directions does not simply result in a bad system of law; it
results in something that is not properly called a legal system at all”
(Fuller 1964, 39).
Fuller’s procedural naturalism is vulnerable to a number of
objections. H.L.A. Hart, for example, denies Fuller’s claim that the
principles of legality constitute an internal morality; according to
Hart, Fuller confuses the notions of morality and efficacy:
[T]he author’s insistence on classifying these principles of legality as a “morality” is a source of confusion both for him and his readers…. [T]he crucial objection to the designation of these principles of good legal craftsmanship as morality, in spite of the qualification “inner,” is that it perpetrates a confusion between two notions that it is vital to hold apart: the notions of purposive activity and morality. Poisoning is no doubt a purposive activity, and reflections on its purpose may show that it has its internal principles. (“Avoid poisons however lethal if they cause the victim to vomit”….) But to call these principles of the poisoner’s art “the morality of poisoning” would simply blur the distinction between the notion of efficiency for a purpose and those final judgments about activities and purposes with which morality in its various forms is concerned (Hart 1965, 1285-86).
On Hart’s view, all actions, including virtuous acts like lawmaking
and impermissible acts like poisoning, have their own internal
standards of efficacy. But insofar as such standards of efficacy
conflict with morality, as they do in the case of poisoning, it follows
that they are distinct from moral standards. Thus, while Hart
concedes that something like Fuller’s eight principles are built into
the existence conditions for law, he concludes they do not constitute a
conceptual connection between law and morality.
Unfortunately, Hart overlooks the fact that most of Fuller’s eight
principles double as moral ideals of fairness. For example, public
promulgation in understandable terms may be a necessary condition for
efficacy, but it is also a moral ideal; it is morally objectionable for
a state to enforce rules that have not been publicly promulgated in
terms reasonably calculated to give notice of what is required.
Similarly, we take it for granted that it is wrong for a state to enact
retroactive rules, inconsistent rules, and rules that require what is
impossible. Poisoning may have its internal standards of efficacy, but
such standards are distinguishable from the principles of legality in
that they conflict with moral ideals.
Nevertheless, Fuller’s principles operate internally, not as moral
ideals, but merely as principles of efficacy. As Fuller would likely
acknowledge, the existence of a legal system is consistent with
considerable divergence from the principles of legality. Legal
standards, for example, are necessarily promulgated in general terms
that inevitably give rise to problems of vagueness. And officials all
too often fail to administer the laws in a fair and even-handed manner
even in the best of legal systems. These divergences may always be prima facie
objectionable, but they are inconsistent with a legal system only when
they render a legal system incapable of performing its essential
function of guiding behavior. Insofar as these principles are built
into the existence conditions for law, it is because they operate as
efficacy conditions and not because they function as moral ideals.
Read "Natural Law by Pauline Westerman" Here.
Read "Natural Law by Pauline Westerman" Here.
0 Comments